Join us for the
2010-11 Technoscience Salon
Open Concept
This year the Salon gathers up scholars, artists, and scientists to spark collective interventions in ways of reckoning with power, relations of exchange, and forms of life in technoscientific worlds. We are propelled by the provocation: What now? What might follow from the conceptual and political labor that has shaped current thinking about the lives and worlds of technoscience? The Open Concept Salons invite you to join us to work intensively and creatively on a series of keywords that have been or might become generative for rethinking relations in technoscience.
Conceptual Practice
Conception means both the formation of thought and the generation of life. Acts of conception and practices of conceptualization produce real material effects. Feminist technoscience scholars remind us that we need to take good care of our concepts. The Open Concept Salon opens up inquiry into the agencies, effects, and affects of concepts, and offers a site for doing the conceptual work of reckoning with what matters in contemporary technoscience. The 2010-11 Salon was organized by Michelle Murphy (UofT), Natasha Myers (York), Emily Simmonds (York), and Sarah Tracy (UofT)
Concepts & Conceptacles :: Friday October 1
-
“…the task Whitehead assigned to philosophy, to design new [concepts], would be a success only if those [concepts] induced an empirically felt elucidation of our experience. …he did not mean the disclosure of the truth of the world, but the empirically felt variation of the way our experience matters, inextricably associating the what of the experience…and its how.” (Stengers, “A constructivist reading of Whitehead, 2008)
This year’s Technoscience Salon is committed to grappling with the power of concepts. In this little meditation on concepts, I look to Isabelle Stenger’s (2008) reading of Alfred North Whitehead. For Whitehead, crafting and refining concepts is our vocation.
Concepts are our constructions. We put our concepts to work to open up the world in new ways, and to experience new moments of what Whitehead in the quote above calls “disclosure.” In other words, concepts open access to worlds and can become prostheses for making sense of worlds.
After Donna Haraway, we might think of concepts as lively material-semiotic actors. Stengers recognizes this power of concepts in her notion of “conceptual agency.” For Stengers, concepts ask for and prompt a “leap of imagination”; they act as a “lure for feeling, for feeling ‘something that matters.’” Concepts tug at our perceptions and in so doing they “vectorize concrete experience” (97). Indeed, as we work with concepts they entangle us in new kinds of relationships with the world. We might then ask: What relations do we want to cultivate? Which do we want to challenge? To go further we can invoke Donna Haraway’s recognition that concept-making is a world building practice. If our concepts are lures that remake the world, the question we need to keep returning to is: What kind of worlds do we want to build?
In addition to cultivating creativity in our conceptual practice, we must also learn how to take care of our concepts. According to Stengers, “Whitehead implies that if we are not prisoners of our abstractions, then we may well become prisoners of the false problems they are bound to create if we extend, outside their specialized domain, the trust they deserve only inside this domain” (2008: 97). Without care and caution concepts are at risk of producing what Whitehead has called “the fallacy of misplaced concreteness.” Concepts can fix the world and constrain thought and relations. Concepts have to be supple; they have to have the dexterity to do the work we set them in motion to do, and they must never be deployed to concretize the flux of the world.
Stengers suggests that we follow Whitehead who treated concepts as engineered devices. They are “appliances” that are carefully designed and deployed. As devices, they have to be tested, revised, reframed, reformatted on an ongoing basis. And yet these “devices” are not dead mechanisms. They can be engaged as what I like to call “lively machines.” In our hands, concepts can become sporulating, germinating machines capable of propagating new forms of life.
Michelle Murphy and I find much inspiration in the connection between concepts and “conceptacles”. According to the Oxford English Dictionary, a conceptacle is defined as an object “in that which anything is contained.” A conceptacle is a vessel or cavity in a body, a cavity-like organ containing the reproductive cells in some plants and animals. Conceptacles are “receptacles” like the propagative follicles that bejewel the fronds of seaweed.
A conceptacle is a tissue; and we can engage this tissue as an infolded assemblage of both matter and meanings. We treat conceptacles as living containers that conceive; that is, conceptacles grow and propagate our concepts. We might expand our understanding of such tissues to think of conceptacles as the containers of our thought collectives and communities. Enfolded, they become the classrooms, meeting halls, and institutions that grow and propagate concepts.
My hope is that the Open Concept Salons initiate inquiry into the relations among concepts and their conceptacles. How do our concepts vectorize bodies, economies, and ecologies? How do our thought collectives assemble and contract around concepts? How do these these collectives ingather to design and propagate new concepts?
-
“Concept” is imbued with sex. It vibrates between the realm of discursive chains and bodies that matter. “To conceive” holds within it both meaning and matter: the generation of ideas and the reproduction of life. So while in academic conversations we might be tempted to corral “concept” into the domain of mentality, it insists on pointing to its lively embodiment.
Adding a suffix, concepts slip into “conceptacles.” Linnaeus, who called himself the Second Adam of the 18th century, naming and ordering life, used the term “conceptacle” to name the container-like reproductive vessels found on many kinds of sea weed. Linnaeus, from whose system is derived our present scientific classifications of life, particularly used plant sex to codify different organisms. Today, sea weed is an algae, yet red algae, corallines, and green fucales are still understood to reproduce through “conceptacles” – tissues of containers, of many sexes, from which enact the generative capacity of algae life. Conceptacles, then are small lively vessels, set in a tissue of other conceptacles, that have the capacity to generate new life. A field of tiny openings.
What would it mean to open “concept” through the figure of the conceptacle?
As Natasha has suggested, much of science studies has moved to see concepts as having agencies that matter. Concepts do things in the world, they form attachments, draw things together, become friends, become crutches or “black boxes”. Concepts are actors who we live among and with.
Here we might note two tempting attractions for how we might think “concept”: 1) concept as immaterial thought form, and 2) concept as generated from material assemblages of practices, instruments and subjects, in turn with their own material effects.
In science and technology studies, we could say that the field has become enchanted with “matter” as an antidote to versions of nominalism, yes, but also perhaps in reaction to the slipperiness of our working material – words – in the academic world that prizes products – commodifiable things. We could even make the grand claim that academics today learn, work and teach in an era of things not words, of visualities not books. To work with concepts is to be swimming upstream. So there is complex anxiety about the work of words – an aspiration that our eloquence helps to take apart and make worlds, joined with the impotence of written drafts squirreled away on harddrives.
Nevertheless from a philosophical angle, from Nietzsche through Deleuze to feminist theorist Elizabeth Grosz, we are enjoined to generate “concepts” as our critical intellectual work. Creating concepts – that do some things, not others, that are open to revision and collective fashioning, that are mobile and recombinable. The more modest work of making concepts displaces a previous ethic of grand “theorizing” – where evidence leads to the jump of explanation (and vice versa) — to a vision of intellectuals and researchers working in the thick of an already knowledge saturated world. Concepts come from being in the middle of relations, not outside or above them. Drawing on Grosz, who is drawing on Deleuze, we might playfully pose the project of making concepts as a project of entering a field of tiny conceptacles, in which:
every conceptacle, as a complex heterogeneity, has components that are themselves concepts, but not only – conceptacles also require bodies , affects, tools, and practices.
Every concept is linked in a tissue of other concepts, which are its history and kin, its forms of contiguity and contingency that make up each concept and its conceptual landscape.
This means that even a slight shift in the relations of these components or neighboring conceptacles, or in the tissue of tiny relations, begins a process of changing a concept.
Thus, conceptacles are not just thoughts or containers, but congealments of relations that can “reproduce” in many ways.
Concept work, as a project in STS and the Technoscience Salon , has , I think, a more modest tenor then “theorizing.” Conceptacles placing us among the people, ideas, organisms, and relationships that are at stake in our research.
Thus, it might be worth noting that there is yetanother tension animating concept-work :
Seeing concept-making as a critical project – as the will to change, to take things apart, to undo and not just make. Here the danger is nihilism.
Valuing concept-work for the way it is productive – conceptacles as animating, putting relations in motion. The danger here is becoming enthralled to the innovation logic of our current moment. Here the temptation is the pull to make new, make again and call new. Concept work is in a dance with the proprietary hold of the author function. I must make something new.
I want to turn now from thinking about “concept” to what happens when we put “open” before concept, as in “Open Concept”
Here I would like to think concept-work as neither an undoing, nor a reinvention, but an opening out and lateral attaching, How might we take seriously the tiny conceptacle as not just generative containers, but a sensitive infrastructure of openings, of tiny risks to being affected by that which we engage?
Yet there is much to be wary of in the pairing of “open” and “concept.” “Open concept” already circulates as a late-twentieth century mode of architecture and a contemporary politics of information. I want to think through these two material examples of “open concept” before returning to the figure of the conceptacle.
In the first, example, “Open Concept” is the name for a mode of arranging office work as the “open plan office.” Developed in the 1960s as way to add more efficiency and flexibility to corporate structures, the open office architects drew on cybernetics to diagram the circuits of information flow that made up the relations in a corporation. These diagrams would inevitably look nothing like the hierarchical pyramid structure of the mid-century company, but instead connect workers across rank, making administrators crucial nodes of information circulation. The office was then redesigned as a more “democratic” and open space, with workers of many ranks grouped together and desks arranged in non-symmetrical landscape of equipment, workers, and partitions.
The “open concept” office was not only intended to make work flow more efficient, it was “flexible,”with the capacity to rearrange workers within the container of the building floor plan. For Robert Propst, one of early promoters of the flexible open concept office, “change” was the new master of office organization. In his 1968 office planning manifesto Change, Propst declared,:
In the past, it was comforting to be part of stable, permanent organizations. Change, with its newness and novelty, was limited to the role of upgrading or improving existing forms. History has taught us to accept the straight line of evolution. We are disturbed by the revolutionary effect of exponential change rates. Undeniably, we are already deeply involved with a new state of reality, a new iron mistress, the exponential change in the rate of change. The office in its relationship to the organization it serves must now obey the dynamic new factors this imposes.
Thus, the project of “open concept” architecture materialized the values of flexibility, dynamism, change. Yet, flexibility and even “participation,” we’ve since learned, are not innocent. By the 1980s, open concept offices were warrens of cubicles, while flexibility enables cost-efficiencies, downsizing, and temporary work forces. To be open was to be flexible and responsive for capital.
In the second example, “open concept” is a phrase used in contemporary debates about datamining and open access information.
For example, the recently formed “Concept Web Alliance” is concerned with how open access information interfaces with practices of relational-databasing and datamining. At stake is how to process information in a world over-rich in data. In genomics alone, there is already more data than could possibly ever be analyzed with current techniques. Data is not overabundant, and beyond the human-scale of apprehension. We can not fully “datamine” our data.
Instead of order and sorting data by categories, the Resource Description Framework (RDF) metadata model uses “triples” to map combinations of the shortest meaningful sentence : subject, predicate, and object. What makes a triple is the relation – the predicate — that holds the triplet together. Such triples are also described as concept-relation-concept. RDF, then, sorts for the relations that attach data, rather than the data itself. Any concept might form part of many triples.
“Open Concept” here names the aspiration of using software to harvest new “concepts” out of this tangle of relations, creating software generated micro-publications as a new form of knowledge production.
Propietary sortware – such as Microsoft’s Amalga software for the life sciences,– aspires to just that. It promises to “accelerate research velocity, create actionable knowledge, and enable organizational agility.” This direction in concept-making software anticipates instantly creating new concepts from relations with other concepts. While Amalga harvests “concepts” from proprietary databases, others see this as the next step in “open” knowledge production that will grow out of open access data, in which software will automate for anyone the task of concept-work.
In these two examples – of the open office and open access data, — to be open is not romantic, but risky. To be open, as an affective condition, in this sense is to be accessible, even unrestricted, free from limitation or regulation, or to be in full view. Thus, to be open is also another aspirational temptation for us. The Salon’s project of “opening concept” is thus a tension filled format. Even algae conceptacles, as sensitive openings, produce vulnerabilities to chemical and particulate pollution.
Perhaps, then, conceptacles invite us to think the task of opening concepts more modestly — as a small door, passage, or entrance into a project of provisionally and carefully holding things, words, and practices and people together, gathered around a table, around a concept, and be open to the risk of what it might do to, through, and with us. What if we let concepts – in all their messy multiplicity and genealogical tensions — move us, and not just see ourselves as “making and unmaking concepts?”
In this spirit, turning to the conceptacle as a figure for thinking “open concept” prompts our attention to 1) the concept as a small and humble formation, within a tangle of other conceptacles; 2) the lively, generative and reproductive capacities of concepts, which put us into question; 3) the care we might take in crafting and entering conceptacles, as the site of concept-work that is always in the middle.; 4) the non-innocence of relations, stakes and attachments, and the risk of openness. What is reproduced in the conceptacle? What arrangements, habits of thought, relations, hierarchies, what recombinatory possibilities for kinship are remade?
Put even more broadly, “open concept” lays bare the question: What is reproduced in Science and Technology Studies? What can be reproduced by inviting in other possibilities for kinship with practices, disciplines, and words, that might come in sideways? Will we risk being moved?
Forgiveness :: Friday October 22
Alexis Shotwell (Laurentian) and Alice MacLachlan (York)
-
Alice writes:
We began with what we take to be a fairly provocative statement by Hannah Arendt about the limits of forgiveness: namely, its inapplicability to contexts of suffering beyond recognizable human agency:
“Because [forgiveness]… can function only under the condition of plurality, it is very dangerous to use this faculty in any but the realm of human affairs. Modern natural science and technology, which no longer observe or take material from or imitate processes of nature but seem actually to act into it, seem, by the same token, to have carried irreversibility and human unpredictability into the natural realm, where no remedy can be found to undo what has been done. Similarly, it seems that one of the great dangers of acting in the mode of making [is]… one is bound not only to do with the means of violence necessary for all fabrication, but also to undo what he has done as he undoes an unsuccessful object, by means of destruction.” – Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition 2nded. (Chicago, 1958) 238.
Arendt’s remarks are so provocative because so many of our actions bring us into relationships of suffering and responsibility with non-human others. How might we think about our capacity to respond to wrongs and responsibilities either without forgiveness – or in ways that challenge Arendt’s refusal to extend it?
Alexis writes:
In my comments I simply dwelled with Donna Haraway’s thinking about suffering and forgiveness.
Haraway begins the chapter “Sharing Suffering” in her When Species Meet with a character from a Nancy Farmer novel who experiments on guinea pigs. As he subjects them to the bites of the tsetse flies, he puts his own arm in range of the painful bites, and in range of the danger of sleeping sickness – the disease he is attempting to stave off. Baba Joseph figures the lab worker who attempts to stand in a relationship of response with the animals he causes to suffer. Haraway quotes his assessment of his own action: “It’s wicked to cause pain, but if I share it, God may forgive me.” I, with Haraway, am interested in what it means to stand in need of forgiveness – and in whether it’s possible to think about forgiveness without an appeal to religion. Should God forgive Baba Joseph? Should the guinea pigs? The flies? The protozoan parasites who might sicken the biting flies and then die? How are relations of use navigated when we try to nurture a capacity to respond and an attitude of sharing the suffering we produce?
The broader questions involve what it means to stand in unforgivable relations, to be positioned such that our existence causes pain, degradation, and suffering to others. This is, arguably, the condition of life for everyone, at every scale: for any one to live, someone(s) die. But it the reality that life involves suffering is particular salient, though perhaps peculiarly difficult to apprehend, for those of us who benefit from or are directly responsible for the suffering of others. Recipients of breast cancer treatments tested on oncomice, for example. Eaters of lobsters recently cooked. Wearers of clothes made at low money-cost and high life-force-cost. People who live on land expropriated from indigenous peoples in ongoing relations of genocide. Buyers of airline tickets through prison-based call-centers where inmates are paid, if they are paid, pennies an hour.
“Baba Joseph’s bitten arm,” Haraway writes, “is not the fruit of a heroic fantasy of ending all suffering or not causing suffering, but the result of remaining at risk and in solidarity in instrumental relationships that one does not disavow.” So, three things from this:
Remaining at risk involves recognizing that response will be required, that what we cultivate in recognizing how we are situated in relation to other beings – lab animals and otherwise – will put us at risk of being called on to be responsible. This involves nourishing our capacities to respond and, significantly, our capacities to transform ourselves through remaining available for response. This is one reason possessive individualism, arising from “entities with fully secured boundaries” will fail as the moral unit involved in circumstances in which we are implicated in suffering. We will need something much more like Karen Barad’s understanding of the intra-action, involving always onto-ethico-political questions. The shape of this morality will be necessarily non-anthropomorphic: human exceptionalism and human reference as strategies for feeling safely absolved, entitled to dominate the natural world, or safe from transformation in virtue of our capacity to reason, won’t fly.
Being in solidarity involves holding difference as primary; relations of self-sameness don’t produce solidarity. Rather, in thinking about lab animals, animals we eat, bugs we kill while growing vegetables, and so on, it is precisely the recognition that there are relevant differences along with relevant samenesses that provokes both the material situation of the guinea pigs (and so on) and the need for ethical response. But to think about solidarity is always to think about the sites of difference while in the same breath standing with the needs, goals, and pleasures of the beings with whom we are entangled in our practices. We are thus aiming for nonmimetic understanding of well-being, suffering, death, while simultaneously seeing ourselves as constituted in the relations we produce.
Not disavowing instrumental relations involves facing up to the fact that we use others: we experiment on them, we cause them pain, we kill them. Normally these kinds of actions, if you did them, are sites at which you would beg forgiveness. And to be forgivable, we might very much expect also that you would pledge to not continue doing the things you wish to be forgiven for. But Baba Joseph wants to find a way to have fewer cows and people die of sleeping sickness, and so those guinea pigs will continue to suffer. He is using them, as all of us are using lab animals somewhere for something we want from them in ways that cause us to ask, even indirectly, for someone to cause them pain and death.
Haraway writes: “The moral sensibility needed here is ruthlessly mundane and will not be stilled by calculations about ends and means. The needed morality, in my view, is culturing a radical ability to remember and feel what is going on and performing the epistemological, emotional, and technical work to respond practically in the face of the permanent complexity not resolved by taxonomic hierarchies and with no humanist philosophical or religious guarantees” (75).
I don’t have a word for how we might systematize this kind of ethics. Haraway explores other people’s practices in labs that point to promising practices for working with this kind of unresolvable, permanent complexity. This will mean being painstaking – taking pains to be response-able, in the moment and its specificity, with the understanding that there is not really an endpoint or a permanent closure, but instead something more terrifying.
“My suspicion is that the kind of forgiveness that we fellow mortals living with other animals hope for is the mundane grace to eschew separation, self-certainty, and innocence even in our most creditable practices that enforce unequal vulnerability” (75).
Alice writes:
I tried to raise some of what I take to be the most puzzling and promising challenges and questions in my research on forgiveness thus far – especially as these relate to atypical or non-paradigmatic contexts of responsibility and suffering:
In my research, I try to think through the ethical and political implications of concepts that are, at once, socially embedded, constituted and negotiated practices for navigating the aftermath of wrongful harm and, also, have – or seem to have – the status of virtues, that is, moral or rational ideals that transcend the social contexts from which they emerge. This second aspect suggests that the logic of forgiveness and its conceptual cousins can tell us something about the content of our obligations and duties, or the claims we might make on others, while the first pushes us to acknowledge that forgiveness or its refusal may only ever make sense within the cultural and social context from which it emerges or is absent.
For many in my field (analytic philosophy) the conceptual double-life of forgiveness can pose a bit of a puzzle, and the temptation to ‘bolster’ the concept with non-contextual, universalistic conditions that, taken together, teach us what ‘true’, ‘genuine’ or ‘moral’ forgiveness might be. I want to theorize forgiveness while resisting this move. Claudia Card’s talk of a ‘moral power’ in The Atrocity Paradigm seems promising, as it allows us to recognize how the power to forgive arises out of shared understandings of roles, capacities and abilities, and suggests that such ‘power’ is vulnerable, even fragile – since it may well depend on another agent’s recognition of that forgiveness. Card’s approach also allows us to value refusals of forgiveness as appropriate acts of power. But ultimately, her construct may not do justice to the ways in which we practice forgiveness, and how practices of forgiveness may vary widely in powerful and problematic ways, particularly when viewed politically.
I take up (promising yet questionable) practices of forgiveness as a way to focus on the roles and relationships that are created by wrongful harm, and the implicit norms, guidelines and calls that together structure these roles and relationships. We can acknowledge Arendt’s cautions about plurality by asking whether the practice of forgiveness is limited to contexts where roles of ‘victim’ and ‘wrongdoer’ make easy sense, when our responsibility for wrongdoing seems to extend past such contexts. Central to my investigation is the question:
How can one person’s responsibility for suffering ever create a call or an obligation on the part of the sufferer? What are we to make of this transmission of responsibility? And how might we turn this call on its head, by thinking about practices of unforgiveness or refusals of forgiveness – as ways of taking and retaining responsibility?
I look to the implications and tensions raised by the metaphors and imagery through which forgiveness is most often articulated: what does it mean to speak of forgiveness as a change of heart? Turning the other cheek? Wiping the slate clean? How can we make sense of seemingly contradictory economies of forgiveness – that, on the one hand, forgiveness concerns the economy of (moral) debt relations and distribution and also, on the other, that forgiveness is an act of generosity, a spontaneous gift? Some have described forgiveness as a way to relieve suffering wrongdoers from the burden of their guilt – but are such burdens ever simply lifted, or are they rather taken on and absorbed by the already-suffering victims of wrong?
I suspect that our rich, implicit, overlapping understandings of forgiveness reveal the choices we make about a number of ethical movements following wrongdoing. I think of these as the possible functions of forgiveness: namely, relief, release and repair:
Release: Does forgiveness release the agent from responsibility or culpability for her action? How can we make sense of such a release – let alone endorse it? Can we see practices of forgiveness in other, more problematic practices of release for wrongdoers: waiving of corporate liability for ecological and human costs of business, political pardons for cronies, unjust practices of imprisonment that excuse those with power or privilege, or national refusals to take responsibility for historic wrongs of internal and external colonialism? Who is empowered to offer such release – and what kind of agency is required to do so? And finally, we might consider whether release from wrong is always, or ever, symmetrical, and what it means when a forgiven wrongdoer refuses to let go. Here I am struck by Alexis’s remarks about instrumental relationships, and what it means to stand at what would ordinarily be a site of forgiveness. Does acknowledging the limits of forgiveness to which Arendt alludes mean conscientiously refusing to release ourselves from these non-instrumental relationships and our role within them? Should we see and understand ourselves as importantly unforgiven?
Relief: Can forgiveness offer relief from the often viscerally physical, material and present harms created by violence, negligence, instrumentality and apathy? How can we make sense of symbolic or social relief for material harms – and for whom and by whom is this relief experienced? We might consider the truism that victims who forgive feel better themselves, and what truths stand behind it. Who else benefits from the relief of forgiveness – besides, potentially, victim and perpetrator – and what kinds of choices should we make about whether relief is deserved or merited?
Repair: Many theorists have argued, convincingly, that forgiveness is valuable because it repairs relationships. What relationship does – or can – forgiveness repair? I think here of Alexis’s account of our entanglement. Thinking about forgiveness may require us to acknowledge relationships that require transformation rather than repair – and to resist assuming more relationality is always better, and dis-identification and distance are always worse – even as we realize we cannot always un-relate ourselves from our entanglements: they are present in our food, our homes, our lives.
We can ask about the dimensions in which forgiveness takes place – whether it is ultimately a kind of social performance or, on the other hand, the emotional transformation of resentment and anger – and how forgiveness is connected to related practices of apology, reparation, punishment and reconciliation. Ultimately, exploring these functions leads us into broader conversations about when and how to place, withhold, or negotiate responsibility for suffering and the very real consequences of our roles in it.
Experiment :: Friday November 12
Natalie Jeremijenko (NYU) and Lucy Suchman (Lancaster)
Propagation :: Friday January 14
Natalie Loveless (UCSC), Shiho Satsuka (UofT) and Joan Steigerwald (York)
Ecology :: Friday February 11
Jaime Yard (York), Carla Hustak (UofT), Shubhra Gururani (York)
-
While ecology is generally understood as intimate environmental relations between entities, I want to disturb this idea by insisting that ecology is also about the making of the nonhuman and human bodies through those relations. In other words, I offer to the salon the provocation of thinking ecologies and ontologies together. For this reason, I have entitled my talk, Eco/ontologies: Machinic Intimacies in the Making of Bodies and Worlds. In keeping with the spirit of the salon’s intellectual play, I want to begin by suggesting that ecology as a concept offers us a unique opportunity to reflect on past salons. We could think of our work here as an ecology of concepts such as experiment, forgiveness, and propagation which have generated questions of the entangled makings of bodies and worlds. I suggest that ecology lends itself to rethinking experiment as the novel mixtures of human and nonhuman actors which test their relatedness with unexpected and surprising results. In our session on forgiveness, we looked at responsiveness and questions of response-ability between actors. This highlights a specific dynamic of ecological relatedness tied to our own concerns over our ethical response-abilities to nonhumans. And, as I will show in my talk, I think of ecology in very close relation to how we played with the concept of propagation. In Natalie Loveless’s talk on propagation, her reference to Isabelle Stengers’ “ecology of practices” hints at this very close connection between propagation and ecology. This is a connection that I want to take the opportunity to further explore in opening up the concept of ecology as a tool to think with.
My use of the phrase eco/ontologies comes from the fifth chapter of my dissertation which explored the connections between early twentieth century sex reform, conservation and preservation movements, and the development of ecology as a discipline. In that chapter, I asked the question of what it meant for ecology to develop in the context of the reproductive politics of sex reform, birth control, and eugenics. My chapter introduced the concept of eco/ontologies to highlight how ecology and reproductive politics informed and shaped one another. As ecology developed, it emerged as a promiscuous discipline, emerging out of an array of sciences such as botany, biology, palaeontology, embryology, biogeography, and zoology. In the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, agricultural science gained considerable prominence in the rise of agricultural experiment stations. These stations were concerned about both environmental factors in the production of crops and the biological, genetic, and engineering of the reproduction of perfect specimens of fruits, vegetables, and flowers. Moreover, these experimental stations such as the Maine Agricultural Experiment Station joined human and nonhuman bodies in their investigations of strategies for reproducing fitter bodies. There were departments in botany, entomology, zoology, and even home economics. In both eugenic and birth control campaigns, reformers and scientists drew on evolutionary discourses to assess whom should mate with whom which cut across similar questions in plant and animal breeding experiments. In this sense, scientists and popular intellectuals invoked racial, class, sexual, and gender hierarchies of power across analyses of the potentialities of human, animal, and plant bodies. The questions of environmental conditions and heredity were entangled in ways that brought together reproductive politics and environmental sciences.
Here, I want to build on this understanding of eco/ontologies to suggest that we can think of ecology as not simply relations between actors but channels of incorporation. I urge that we pay precise attention to the bodies that are made and unmade, attached and unattached, assembled and reassembled as they join and break from networks or communities. As a history of early twentieth century sex reform, my dissertation attended to sex as one such channel of incorporation. More recently, I have turned attention to other channels of incorporation such as digestion and other forms of embodied perception. There are three registers for rethinking ecology in this way; namely, the spatial, temporal, and ontological. Firstly, eco/ontologies challenges our conventional understanding of space by rethinking topographies, strata, maps, proximities, and coordinates as not only the movements of bodies through space but their formation, transformation, and gestation through their movements. Secondly, eco/ontologies also raise questions of temporality in terms of the speeds and intensities through which bodies relate to one another and travel in historical, present, and anticipated future time. Thirdly, and perhaps most importantly, eco/ontologies is a question of how human and nonhuman bodies are inter-implicated in the becomings of bodies and worlds.
Luciana Parisi’s views of “technoecologies of sensation” presents an important lens for exploring how ecological sensibility is also about the kinds of bodies we become. Parisi’s essay which appears in Deleuze/Guattari/Ecology argues that our present is shaped by informational technologies which are re-crafting sensory regimes. In doing so, Parisi insists that our technoscientific present is marked by modes of gathering information such as digitalization, media technologies, and DNA sequencing which are redefining bodily experience. Beginning her essay with Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari’s concept of involution, Parisi draws attention to information gathering as open-ended, transformative, fluid, and unstable relations among diverse bodies. Parisi indicates that this ecology can encompass human flesh, bacteria, silicon, neural connections, and equations. To think with Parisi about ecology is to think machinically. According to Parisi, “to think machinically is to engage with technical machines in terms of semi-concatenations of partial objects running through strata.” (Parisi, 183) Parisi suggests that ecological relations are formed between bodies that are always fragmented, unfinished, and only temporarily defined by their momentary attachment to a particular community, network, or relationship. Using the geological metaphor of strata, Parisi disturbs a concept of ‘nature’ and invokes a ‘machinism of nature’ as the crossing and promiscuous intermixing of seemingly separate levels of ontology. Parisi draws on a view of strata that is inspired by Deleuze and Guattari’s “Geology of Morals” where strata are temporary thresholds or plateaus held in suspended animation. What is important to grasp here is that ontology and ecology are critically joined as the shaky, unstable grounds of the ‘natural’ body and ‘natural’ space.
While Parisi helps us to broaden our perspective on ecology to encompass metal and bacteria as much as plants, animals, and humans, her “technoecologies of sensations” can also help us rethink much of what we take for granted as an abstractness of information. Instead, Parisi suggests that we look at digitalization, DNA calculations, logarithms, and velocities as embodied information. She, in fact, simultaneously joins bodies and information as information sensing, specifically denoted by her terms “bio-logic” and “bio-informatics.” Parisi’s technoecologies of sensation are worlds of the blending and motions of human bodies, nonhuman bodies, and information. In doing so, Parisi emphasizes the interpenetration of bodies and information in these mediatic, sensory, fleshy and mathematically calculated environments, Parisi states that there is “a whole ecology of machines traversing substantial scales: mental, natural, social, technical dimensions ceaselessly code, drift, side-communicate across space and time.” (Parisi, 183) These drifts are also ontological drifts highlighted by Parisi’s examples of bionic retinas, DNA biochips, and corporeal prosthetics where sensation is not simply extended by machines but transformed into machinic sensing. Moreover, Parisi indicates that in our technoscientific present these machinic intimacies are not one way. According to Parisi, machines also carry sensory capacities which we can see in measuring respiration, cameras that see us, and the tactile detection of bodies. In other words, Parisi’s view of the ‘bio-logical’ and ‘bio-informatics’ implicates the seemingly abstract worlds of concepts, mathematics, and information in the messy, fleshy, and earthy worlds of human and nonhuman (re)productions.
In addition to helping us rethink spatiality and information, Parisi’s “technoecologies of sensation” also help us re-conceptualize the body. Parisi moves us to a vision of the body itself as a technoecology of sensation with interpenetrating stratas of touch, sight, taste, sound, and smell and nodes of communication such as skin and guts that register intimacies with the world beyond the body. What Parisi calls symbiosensation identifies the body as a complex interactive regime with multiple levels and parts that open the body to networks beyond itself. According to Parisi, symbiosensation is the “kinesthetic sensibility feels the movements of the body as if in strict resonance with the velocities of information sensing captured by the skin and guts.” (Parisi, 191) This, I argue, is a clear example of channels of incorporation where information is not only registered on the skin and in the guts but evokes the body’s process of becoming with the world. Parisi further elucidates symbiosensation as the “in-depth sensibility proper to involutionary infoldings of matter: a proto-feeling preceding and exceeding the organization of information sensing into neurosensorial channels.”(Parisi, 195) If we take Parisi’s symbiosensation seriously, environmental politics can be joined to the sexual and racial politics of redefining bodies as agentic, intelligent, and machinic which reclaim materiality as a promising zone of transformable possibilities.
As a historian, I find Parisi’s “technoecologies of sensation” a useful tool for thinking about the historicity of feeling. Parisi’s work gestures toward thinking of temporal shifts in sensory experience by making the claim that we are witnessing profound transformations in our sensory regimes. This raises the possibility for considering the historical specificity of sensory experience. However, at the same time, Parisi’s emphasis on technoecologies as a current phenomenon also undercuts the possibilities for considering the applicability of the concept technoecologies of sensation to other historical periods. I would suggest that this move also has the effect of suggesting that nature was somehow less machinic in the past. Instead, I would argue that Parisi’s “technoecologies of sensation” could be seen as applicable to the very moment of ecology’s inception as a discipline, albeit with different concepts, different materials, different bodies, and certainly different political and ethical agendas.
Logistics :: Friday March 4
Joe Masco (U of Chicago) and Deborah Cowen ( UofT)
-
Logistics is a ‘middle child’ concept: stuck between strategy and tactics it needs more attention. Desperately.
Logistics is a word that most of us use, but few know what it ‘really’ means. Logistics has dramatically reshaped the world of highly complex socio-technical systems, yet ironically, in its popular meaning logistics is the execution after thought. It denotes precisely the residual and uncomplicated tasks that need dooing once the sexy work of strategy is done. It its popular usage, logistics is grunt work, it’s the gapers job, it is driving the truck, moving the box, stocking the shelf. Logistics is just getting shit done. It is precisely that which does not require interrogation.
Many would be surprised by logistics’ other meanings and its long, complicated technoscientific life. In this other life, logistics has become tremendously important. To professional practitioners logistics is simply awesome. Industry experts tell us that logistics is everywhere; it is trans, inter, and post. It cuts edges, crosses boundaries and most certainly works outside the box. Note the spatial metaphors. Logistics is about (just-in) time, and it is most definitely about (global) space.
But to its analysts and theorists, logistics is not simply important; logistics has gradually become the how that shapes the what.Logistics has come to lead strategy and tactics: it has gone from being the practical after-thought to the calculative practice that defines thought. Jomini asserted the growing importance of logistics in warfare as early as the 1870s, though it was really with the development of the petroleum fueled battlefield that logistics became the driving force of military strategy. DeLanda explains that by WWI, transporting troops, technologies, and the fuel for both to the front gained greater importance; logistics ascended from a residual to commanding role in military strategy.
In a second crucial transformation logistics has gone from military art to business science, even as it also clearly continues to be practiced by the military. The etymology of logistics is often traced to the Greek, ‘logistikos’, meaning ‘skilled in calculating’. The modern life of logistics is very clearly a military life – one of the three arts of Napoleonic warfare along with strategy and tactics, concerned with getting material and men to the front. It was essential for the building of national and colonial power. Yet, today logistics is at the centre of an entangled web of ‘rough trade’, integral to military and civilian practice.
What is likely the most under-investigated revolution of the 20th century, the 1960s ‘revolution in logistics’ reshaped economic calculation and the space economy. This was not a revolution of one country or political system, but rather in the calculation and organization of circulation. The single most important shift in logistics thought and practice in the early postwar period came with the introduction of a systems analysis. Systems analysis served to re-scale the space of action and redefined logistics as the spatial management of production and distribution rather than a discrete function that followed manufacturing. The revolution in logistics shifted the managerial focus from cost-savings in distribution to profit- maximization across the entire system of circulation.
The revolution in logistics thought was underpinned by revolutionary technologies; the container and the computer were key (and both had important early lives in the military). The revolution in logistics can furthermore be understood as a vital calculative underpinning of globalization, even as it remains a critical technology of military operation. Indeed, logistics has not been purified by its civilian rebirth. In fact, it has become increasingly impossible to disentangle the military and civilian threads in the assemblage of rough trade that is at once involved in the delivery of sneakers and smart bombs.
If ‘post-revolutionary’ logistics has become the how that shapes the what, then in a sense this is a claim on the persistent need to ask whose how? And, for what?
Medias in res :: Friday April 22
Melissa Atkinson-Graham (York), Sebastián Gil-Riaño (UofT), and Marc Lafleur (York)
Open Concept Opening Party, 4-6 p.m.@ Magpie, 831 Dundas Street West
Michelle Murphy (UofT), Joe Dumit (UC Davis), and Natasha Myers (York)